Define dual#
Define order-theoretic dual#
Consider the following not-adjoint pair for the SierpiÅski space defined by the open sets \(ā ā \{1\} ā \{0,1\}\), with the closure operator in blue and the interior operator in red. These are not an adjoint pair (take \(p = q = \{1\}\)) despite these operators being described as ādualā to each other in Interior algebra. The full counterexample:
Why does this not work? Weāll come back to this later, but for now letās address why we sometimes expect the word ādualā to imply āadjointā but not the opposite. The simplest way of using the word ādualā is arguably in the sense of Duality (order theory). In fact, this is the meaning used in the first example in Duality (mathematics) Ā§ Introductory examples and in the first section of this article, namely Duality (mathematics) Ā§ Order-reversing dualities. Hereās an example of a duality in this sense:
Weād call the top poset in this example the ādualā (or opposite) of the bottom poset, and vice-versa. Our author uses \(P^{op}\) for this dual poset, but an alternative notation is \(P^d\), which may be more appropriate when you are using the word ādualā regularly (or just to save a letter).
Letās say instead that we were given these two posets and asked if they are duals. In that case weād check that there is an Order isomorphism between one and the dual of the other.
The drawing of the posets above is a special case of duality showing a self-dual poset; there is an order isomorphism between the poset and its own dual. The following poset is not self-dual (derived from this example):
Every order isomorphism is also a galois connection (a strictly weaker notion). So in general we can expect an order duality to lead to an adjoint pair, but not the opposite.
Let \(A\) represent some predicate we can apply to an element that has a dual concept, and call the dual predicate \(A^d\). For example if we let \(A(x)\) mean āx is a greatest elementā then \(A^d(x)\) means āx is a least elementā in a particular poset. Then it should be no surprise that \(A(x) = A^d(x^d)\) where \(x^d\) refers to the element that \(x\) maps to in the opposite category (e.g. \(e\) is mapped to \(e'\) above so that \(-'\) could be thought of as \(-^d\)).
If a concept is āself-dualā then \(A = A^d\) so that \(A(x) = A(x^d)\). If you take \(A\) to mean ā\(āx,y,z: xā§(y āØ z) = (xā§y) āØ (xā§z)\)ā (from Distributive lattice) then \(A = A^d\). If you take \(A\) to mean āis a partial orderā then \(A = A^d\) though weāre now talking at a higher level, so that \(A(X) = A(X^d) = A^d(X^d)\).
We use \(f\) and \(g\) in the drawing above for the two components of an order isomorphism, but because the poset is self-dual we could have also denoted these both as \(-^d\) or \(-^{op}\) and thought of them as endomorphisms. Itās when we have an underlying self-dual order that authors tend to use \(-^c\) (for complement) or \(-^*\) (for pseudocomplement). Unfortunately Ā¬ is also used for both these concepts and must be interpreted based on context.
Define categorical dual#
See Dual (category theory), which is a strict generalization of order-theoretic duality. To take an order-theoretic dual you reverse all arrows (use the opposite order) and switch out order-theoretic definitions such as ā§ and āØ. To take a categorical dual you similarly take the opposite order i.e. reverse all arrows. You also similarly switch out category-theoretic definitions; e.g. the order-theoretic task of switching out ā§ and āØ corresponds to the category-theoretic task of switching out products with coproducts (or limits with colimits). A category is more than an order, however, so there are additional concepts to switch out. For example, many category-theoretic concepts involve composition and the dual conversion requires that composition be reversed.
Define logical dual#
See Duality (mathematics) Ā§ Duality in logic and set theory and let \(A\) mean āinteriorā and \(B\) mean āclosureā in the first definition. Letās take our example from above and replace āinteriorā with the āinterior of the complementā and āclosureā with ācomplement of the closureā to get an adjoint pair with the opposite category:
Apparently, this is the definition of ādualā the authors of Interior algebra had in mind when they described these operators as being dual to each other despite linking to Duality (order theory).
TODO: This may be completely wrong/unhelpful in its current form. Perhaps just remove it. Think of both \(A\) and \(A^d\) as maps to an Ī© such as Bool instead.